With regard to Jensens equality (before continuity is applied) where F(0)=0 and (and F(1)=1 if need be, which is not required );

Jensen's equation beingF(x+y)/2=F(x)/2 +F(y)/2

Is this literally equivalent to cauchy's functional equation F(x+y)=F(x)+F(y) over all rationals in the non quite--continuous case?,

That is continuity and linearity immediate for a jensen's function that satisfies this

(1)F:[0,1] to [0,1]

(2)F(0)=0 F(1)=1

(3)\forall(x,y)\in dom(F):F(x/2+y/2)=F(x)/2 +F(y)/2

That is, one does not have to assume anything, further such  mono-tonicity, bounded on a set of positive measure, continuity, continuity at a point etc.     As in cauchy equation with non negative domain/positive domain and non-domain positive range, with F(1)=1 continuity is apparently automatic.

I am aware that derive 'cauchy's equation from jensen's equation. And i know how that is done. But jensen's equation is different, and works in a slightly different way, by averaging and halving, so even if they are equivalent, 'for all extents and purposes, " are they literally logically equivalent in the strongest sense of word. It appears to be slighly more indirect, and moreover a global, pair-wise result.

For example I know that on closed intervals, midpoint convexity may have trouble with rational convexity (as opposed to dyadic convexity) although I presume that this only an issue due to the inequalities involved. So I presume that if they are truly equivalent under F(0)=0, one should be able to express jensen's function. Whilst in its non continuous (or not necessarily continuous form) it should therefore be able to express real valued additivity, (including any irrational or transcendental), as can cauch'ys equation in the not necessarily continuous case, even if it can only express (just like cauchy's equation) express rational homogeneity, and one cannot directly read their values off via the unit event.

Rationall homogeineity weak \forall x\in dom(F)[0,1] cap rational/dyadic rational: F(x)=x

Generally if a function F; F(x)=x for all rationals or all dyadics, (a dense set of the domain) t

hen it, agrees with, and  is identical  and continious and to, the identity function, on the open interval (0,1) given, that 'F is monotonically increasing' or strictly monotonically increasing'

The identity function being over all reals x [0,1]G(x)=x  ), and  it is considered to be identical to G(x)=x  but  F(x) is monotonically increasing, is not presumed.but here its not even presumed.

So I presume there must be a distinction between showing that F(x)=x for all x, in [0,1] for rational x rationals or all dyadic rationals, which then require monotonicity and the addition of the end points F(0)=0 and F(1)=0 and perhaps the continuity at those pts as well.  So

I presume that both this function and cauchy's function are stronger in another sense 'than being rationally homogeneous in this weaker sense that F(x)=x for all rationals in [0,1];

I also presume that they are both stronger then rational homogeniety in the traditional sense,(2)

Rational homogeneity traditional

F:[0,1] to [0,1]

F(1)=1; F(0)=0 (if not already explcit)

\(2)forall x in the dom(F)[0,1];forall rational \delta (in [0,1] )F(\delta x)=\delta F(x)

which given F(1)=1 entails the F(x)=x for all rationals but is slightly stronger, as it expresses some of relation between irrationals functional values for irrational x,y, F(x), F(y),  that rational multiples of each other. But apart from that its not real valued additive, when one considers irrational values x,y,which are not rational multiples of each other or their sum, whether their sum x+y , is rational or not,. The irrationals, y, are only bounded to be at best, 1>f(y)>0 and worst 1>=F(y)>=0. Even if its presumed F is injective in addition, or bijective I suppose it will guarantee 1>f(y)>0 , and that the irrationals do not take on rational values or that distinct irrational take on the same value but their order may be somewhat out of wack for some x>y, where both are irrational, if they are not mulitples of each other, or otherwise indirectly connected to each other through this relation F(y)> F(x) despite x>y, So I presume that jensens equation and cauchy's equation implies strict monotonicity in the above case for all real values; not just strict monotonicitity over all rationals and best F injective, over all reals, irrationals are 1>F(x)>0; or instead of injectivity-

or something stronger then mere monotonicity (not strict monotonicity for all reals) ; 1>F(x)>0, strictly monotonic for all rationals and F(x)=x for all rationals, as well as rational homogeneity (2) above; as the for distinct irrational x>y F(x)=F(y) if not connected by rational multiples.

So I presume that is the real valued additivity that connected the values together where addivitity apllies for F(x+y) x,y irrational x+y (rational or irrational) and x,y are not rational multiples of each other. Which some how constraints and connects all of the real values together to imply order preservation (strict monotonicity)

, which  given F(1)=1  entails the weaker (1); F(x)=x for all rationals but a bit more. but which does not entail cauchy's equation, or jensens equation, real valued additivity

as \forall real(x,y) in the domain \forall sigma, sigma2 in [0,1]cap Q F(\sigma x +\sigma2 =x)=\sigma_1 F(x)+sigma 2 F(y). or forall sigma, sigma2 in the non-negative rationals Q ; where sigma _1 +sigma 2 are not restricted to sum to one, as F(0)=0 as one recover cauchy equation from that by setting sigma_1=1 and sigma 2=1

Where this generalizes to :for all real(x,y) in the domain \for all sigma_i in {[0,1]cap Q} F(\sum^n_i \sigma i x_i)=\sum^n_i \(sigma_i \timesF(x_i)) ; (Q being the rationals)

where n can be arbitrarily large and where sigma_i are not confined to sum to one, so one can then derive F(0)=0, as one will not get F(0)=1\times F(0) as one does when sigma i must sum to one, as in the convexity and concavity equation. And can one one can recover cauch'sy equation from setting both sigma_i=1; as a result of F(0)=0 it should also entail

which is the alleged super-position principle in rational form and where this really applies for any interval not just [0,1] cap Q depending on the domain of the function, so long as \sum^n_i \sigma i x_i)\in [0,1], so one of the sigm_i could be ten (it really follows from homogeneity from 1/10) in any case);

\forall real(x,y) in the domain \forall sigma, sigma2 in [0,1]cap Q F(\sigma x +\sigma2 =x)=\sigma_1 F(x)+sigma 2 F(y)= F(\sigma _1 x)+F(\sigma _2 x)

On other hand if this all correct, I can have difficulty seeing the purpose of automorphism equations or saying that linearity is cauchy's equation plus continuity when for all extents and purpoes it could be summarized as cauchy's equation. If in probabilistic context, if one get to cauchy's equation where there is always generally a natural unit F:[0,1] to [0,1] then continuity is immediate.

 

More William Balthes's questions See All
Similar questions and discussions