12 December 2017 93 3K Report

In textbooks or introductory texts on quantum mechanics, one may read that the quantum mechanical wave function changes by two fundamentally different processes. One is the deterministic and continuous evolution according to the Schrödinger equation, the other the collapse provoked by a measurement, usually discontinuous, nonlocal and disruptive. I would like to argue that this is due to overburdening the wave function in the Schrödinger picture by requiring it to describe both the state and the dynamics of a system.

The first version of modern quantum mechanics, "matrix mechanics" given in 1925 by Heisenberg, did not do this. Actually, the notion of a wave function was not present in it, even though we may nowadays apply it to Heisenberg's state concept. In the Heisenberg picture, the wave function describes only the initial state of a system. It does not change in time, only on measurement. This change is due to a change in knowledge about the system and the necessity to adapt the probability amplitude to the new knowledge and it corresponds to the collapse. But it is not a dynamical change.

Dynamics is described by the time dependence of observables, i.e. operators. It is governed by Heisenberg's equation of motion, an equation that is equivalent to the Schrödinger equation. So in the Heisenberg picture, dynamics and collapse are neatly separated. Also, the collapse of the wave function cannot be said to be due to a wave packet interacting with a detector, because the wave packet does not change in time, it never gets close to a detector, if it is far from all of them initially. It is, in fact, not a spatiotemporal wave, it is just a spatial distribution. Interaction and dynamics is between observables only. States only describe initial conditions.

Experimental observations neither concern states nor operators directly. They always refer to matrix elements, involving both. So the Schrödinger and Heisenberg pictures are equivalent, giving the same matrix elements. Nevertheless, they attribute the dynamics to different entities.

The Heisenberg picture was invented before the Schrödinger equation. Moreover, it is closer to classical mechanics in that it is straightforward to get from Hamilton's classical equations of motion to the Heisenberg equation of motion, as soon as we know how to quantize phase space functions. Once we know how to construct quantum mechanical operators, all we have to do is to replace phase space functions by operators and the Poisson brackets of classical mechanics by i \hbar times the commutator. The way to the Schrödinger equation is more convoluted. Nevertheless, essentially everybody dashed at the Schrödinger equation, once it became available in 1926, and it soon became the predominant description. Only when we are dealing with multiple-time correlation functions, we prefer the Heisenberg picture, because the consideration of multiple-time correlations functions is difficult to justify in the Schrödinger picture (where the operators whose correlations are of interest remain time independent), whereas it has a clear motivation in the Heisenberg picture.

The reason for this rush at Schrödinger's bonanza obviously was that people knew well how to work with partial differential equations but were unfamiliar with infinite-dimensional matrices. Which then led to the (doubtful) enterprise of assigning more meaning to the wave function than follows from physical considerations.

Consider wave-particle duality, for example. There is a tendency among physicists to overemphasize one of these classical limiting ways for a quantum object "to express itself". Bohmianists give the particle aspect ontological dominance. The wave function is an additional ingredient, but when we measure a quantum particle, we always measure a positional aspect (a pointer variable), and so it is a particle, and the wave is there only to guide it. Others tend to say there is only waves and their interactions with detectors are such that a particle illusion is created. There is the fraction of field theorists saying that there are no particles, only fields, but there are also some serious scientists emphasizing "field theory without fields" by pointing out that the whole physics of a field theory is present in its particle contents.

What does the Heisenberg picture suggest on the question of wave-particle duality? The dynamical entities in the Heisenberg picture are operators. Those are neither particle nor wave. The position operator does not describe an object at a particular position. It has a spectrum containing all possible positions. When it evolves in time (because it is time-dependent in the Heisenberg picture), the relative weights of the positions and, in particular, the expectation value of the position change. But the property "position", as described by the position operator, is not univalent. So the quantum object having that dynamical property cannot be a localized particle that has only one position. On the other hand, the property wave vector is proportional to the momentum operator, evolving in time, too, and having more than one momentum value in its spectrum. The quantum object having that dynamical property cannot be a wave, not a "pure" one at least, characterized by a single wave vector (or a narrow spectrum of such wave vectors). If we take the fact at face value that dynamical variables in quantum mechanics are described by operators, it immediately becomes clear, that the quantum objects are neither waves nor particles but something different -- that's why their description is by operators. Note that in the Heisenberg picture, the double slit experiment gives the same result as in the Schrödinger picture, even though no wave is moving around there (the wave function keeps its initial distribution throughout the experiment until detection of the quantum object). What is changing are the "position" and "momentum" of the quantum object and these are influenced by the presence of both slits. Because they take into account a whole set of possibilities. (The third formulation of quantum mechanics, Feynman's path integral approach turns this set into the possible paths of particles.)

What are quantum objects? Quantum objects are characterized by their properties, as are classical objects. Properties such as mass and charge are simple parameters for the elementary objects as in classical mechanics, whereas dynamic properties such as position and momentum are characterized by operators and hence different for quantum objects from corresponding properties in classical objects. Only in certain limiting cases, described by certain experimental arrangements (forcing their expression), will those properties be close enough to classical ones to characterize a microscopic quantum object as either a particle or a wave. Of course, nothing is to be objected against the notion of "particle" as a shortcut in describing certain quantum objects -- it is much too clumsy to talk in all these cases of "elementary microscopic quantum object". One just has to be aware of the fact that the notion of particle then has a double meaning, one just characterizing elementary object, the other emphasizing localization and particle-like behavior.

Now here is my question. In view of the Heisenberg picture and considering that interpretations of quantum mechanics should be compatible with both the Schrödinger and Heisenberg picture, can the collapse of the wave function be considered a dynamical process?

Similar questions and discussions