https://www.researchgate.net/publication/270687116_AXIOMATIC_THEORY_of_ECONOMICS

This paper provides a simplified exposition (no real analysis) of the economic theory presented in the second part of my 1999 book, Axiomatic Theory of Economics.  It makes no mention of the first part of my book about the foundations of economics.  In this question we will discuss my three-term system of formal logic, specifically with comparison to the attached paper by Steve Faulkner, which was posted in reply to another question that I recently asked.

http://www.researchgate.net/publication/282647562_Logical_independence_inherent_in_Elementary_Algebra_seen_in_context_of_quantum_randomness

In Section 4.3 of my 1999 book I write:

“The great crack in the foundation of mainstream logic where first-sense and third-sense truth are confused has been resolved.  Whenever mainstream logic speaks of affirmation they refer to phenomena having been observed that conform to a definition (truth in the first sense) and whenever they speak of negation they refer to the impossibility of phenomena conforming to a definition (falsity in the third sense).  The three senses of truth must be strictly separated…”

The three sense of truth are defined in an earlier section of my book, but suffice it to say that I was not bothered so much by the paradoxes that Gödel addressed but by the fact that, if p is impossible, the statement “some p are q” is false while the statement “all p are q” is true.  This is absurd.  If I told you that all red-headed Eskimos can foresee the future, a logician would have to admit that, within his science, this statement is true.  But everybody else would denounce me as a lunatic:  Eskimos do not have red hair and nobody – regardless of the color of their hair – can foresee the future.  The logical truth value of my statement will not inspire anybody to travel to Alaska to find Sibyl the Eskimo with her flaming red hair.

“A new system of formal logic will now be introduced.  The three terms of this system of logic are P for possible, I for impossible and M for maybe (similar to Zen Buddhism’s mu.)  Following are eleven logical relations concerning the definitions p and q.  These statements are followed by a truth table which shows, in each of the four situations with which one could be presented when observing phenomena’s conformance to p and q, whether the statement affirms its possibility, its impossibility, or says nothing about that situation.”

While I do not have space here to print the entire list of eleven logical relations, I will print the truth table for “p is possible unless q is possible” to give a taste of what I am doing:

Do phenomena conform to definition p?                T   T   F   F

Do phenomena conform to definition q?                T   F   T   F

p is possible unless q is possible                            I   P   M  M

I then use an example from Willard Quine’s Methods of Logic (p. 196) to illustrate how my method works:

Premises:

1)  The guard searched all who entered the building except those who were accompanied by members of the firm.

2)  Some of Fiorecchio’s men entered the building unaccompanied by anyone else [unaccompanied by non-Fioreccio men].

3)  The guard searched none of Fioreccio’s men.

Using my system, by filling in a truth table with P (possible), I (impossible) and M (maybe), we can quickly determine if the statement, “Some of Fioreccio’s men are members of the firm” is proven.  There is no room to print this here, but it is a sixteen-column truth table with four rows of P, I or M for each of the three premises and the relation, “people who work for Fioreccio.”  Below this is another row labeled “result.”

“Now, filling in an I wherever we see one, a P wherever we see one that is not dominated by an I, and an M only where no statement is made either way, we get the result.”

This is in contrast to Dr. Quine’s method (p. 199), which only proves or disproves one statement at a time.  I write:

“From this result [the three-term truth table] one can test the truth of any conclusion one is interested in…  If we were interested in knowing whether the statement ‘All of Fiorecchio’s men entered the building unaccompanied by non-Fiorecchio men’ is implied by the premises, we would need [elaborate what is needed that we do not know] so the conclusion is not proven; it is a maybe.  This is a more insightful ‘maybe’ than we had before analysis, however, as we now know where our investigation must lead.”

REFERENCES

Quine, W.V.  1982.  Methods of Logic.  Cambridge, MA:  Harvard University Press

Chapter Simplified Exposition of Axiomatic Economics

Article Logical independence inherent in Elementary Algebra seen in ...

More Victor J Aguilar's questions See All
Similar questions and discussions