Donald Davidson began his famous article, Truth Rehabilitated, by lowering the expectations of those who regard the concept of truth as a too venerable concept:
"Before it could come to seem worthwhile to debunk truth, it was necessary to represent truth as something greater than it is, or to endow it with powers it does not have" (2005, p. 4).
Something similar happened in Kant's answer to the skeptic about pure reason. The author coordinated his defense to a lowering of the dogmatist's expectations. For him, part of the problem would be to expect acrobatic - or dialectical - metaphysical performances from reason.
In this little discussion that I would like to start, I would like to put the question inside out. The question today is whether too much was lost, if the loss is not too great, when we accept to level pure reason down, so that it doesn't feel too much pressure.
Even among the heirs of transcendental philosophy there is a feeling that certain canonizations of the conceptual apparatus used for knowing and judging are unnecessary mystifications of something far less venerable. This less venerable something has been named in several descriptions of cultural and anthropological formation, but we can summarize it for economic purposes as the presence of man as a problem unto himself.
The inevitable conclusion-which we see confirmed by the essay-is that this skepticism about rational practice is indeed compatible with transcendental philosophy. Kant could not avoid it. The question can be divided into a set of sub-problems: How much can you give the skeptic without taking it all?
... this demystification of immutable rationality, and its exchange for one linked to the historical and human problem, is an obstacle to a vision of strong rationality, which is above mere habit and bias?
The German and French traditions that emerged from the offshoot of Hegelianism led to the dismantling of the instruments of rationality typically associated with the stability of our political regimes. A post-Hegelian tradition that developed through Marx, the Frankfurt School, and later Foucault set out to change our sociological understanding to look less reverently at legal institutions and other great works of "logos" and to observe the microdramaturgies of power that underlie dominant narratives.This all led to frustration for a group of more traditional philosophers, both epistemologists and semanticists, who still saw logic as an independent and unconstructed (a-historical) form of expression of rationality. Even in American or Anglophone traditions this thought found support, as in Richard Rorty. Great thinkers like D.C. Stove attacked Hume, seeing him as perhaps the most dangerous among the founders of this reasoning. As you have noticed, this has led many, at the limit, to question the role of philosophical questions in general, and to raise the suspicion that what appears as "philosophy" at one time is just the superstructural surface of "Reason" legitimazing self-image, hiding a dramaturgy of more “humane”problems. Debate:
I have separated these brief sections from an article I am trying to write to assess the extent to which our plea for a strong conception of rationality is still possible in a perspective necessarily conditioned by the Kantian (postmetaphysical) conception of pure reason. I would be grateful if interested parties could set forth their own interpretation of this state of affairs and how they believe it is possible for reason to defend itself against skeptical attacks, either within a well-defined, unchanging conceptual zone of categories or outside of it, from a historical and changing perspective of rational parameters. I would also be grateful if you would point out to me the limits of the framework I am using for the discussion.